Notice that in each of the examples in
Section 19.1, the notion of “is smaller than” is defined via a relation. We will use
on
as our model for a relation on a set that can be thought of as expressing “is smaller than or equal in size to.”
Every element in the set should be “smaller than or equal to” itself, so the relation should be
reflexive.
Relative size should
never be bidirectional for distinct elements in the set, so the relation should be
antisymmetric.
We should be able to infer size relationships from chains of them, so the relation should be
transitive.
Notice that these are the same properties as for an equivalence relation,
except that we have flipped
symmetric to
antisymmetric. Make sure to keep this straight!
- partial order
a relation that is reflexive,
antisymmetric, and transitive
- partially ordered set
a set equipped with a particular partial order
symbol for an abstract partial order
- strictly less/smaller than
is strictly less/smaller than
Example 19.2.5. Comparing cardinalities.
Suppose
is a universal set, and consider the collection of
finite subsets of
Then we have a natural way to compare sizes of these subsets: write
to mean
However, this relation is not a partial order as it is not antisymmetric. This is because it is possible to have both
and
with
in the case that
Changing the relation to mean
doesn’t help, since then it wouldn’t be reflexive.
Now suppose the universal set
is infinite and consider
all (hence possibly infinite) subsets of
In this case we have a more general idea of
smaller and
larger, where
is smaller than
if there exists an injection
but no bijection
This more general notion of size comparison via cardinality suffers the same flaws as in the finite set case, as it is not reflexive, and if we try to fix that by adding “or same size as” then it will not be antisymmetric.
However, in both finite and (possibly) infinite cases, we
can turn cardinality comparison into a partial order using “smaller than or
equal to”, where “smaller” must mean strictly smaller in terms of cardinality, but “equal” means
equality of sets rather than equality of cardinality.