Skip to main content
Logo image

Section 2.2 Propositional calculus

Logical equivalence gives us something like an β€œequals sign” that we can use to perform logical β€œcalculations” and manipulations, similar to algebraic calculations and manipulations. To enable us to do such calculations, we first need a β€œtool chest” of basic logical equivalences to use therein.

Example 2.2.3. DeMorgan.

Using Rule 9.b of Proposition 2.2.1, the following are equivalent statements.
  1. The triangle can’t be both right and equilateral.
  2. The triangle is not right or it is not equilateral.
To see how the rule applies, let p represent the statement β€œthe triangle is right” and let q represent the statement β€œthe triangle is equilateral.” Then the first statement above is Β¬(p∧q), while the second statement above is Β¬p∨¬q.
Now we need some new substitution rules to enable us to use the rules of Proposition 2.2.1 in logical calculations.
  1. Think of X as an intermediate column in the calculation of the truth table of A. Replacing X by Y does not change this column, as the truth tables of X and Y are the same.
  2. We leave this statement for you, the reader, to consider. (Again, think of the Ci as intermediate columns in the calculations of the truth tables of Aβ€² and Bβ€².)
Here is an example of a string of logical manipulations. It also demonstrates the use of Rule 10.a of Proposition 2.2.1 to manipulate an expression involving a conditional.

Example 2.2.6. DeMorgan with a conditional.

Consider the statement (p1∨p2)β†’q. We may read it as β€œif either p1 or p2 is true, then q will be true as well.” So it seems that each of p1 and p2 must imply q on its own. Let’s see what propositional calculus says about this:
(p1∨p2)β†’q⇔¬(p1∨p2)∨q(i)⇔(Β¬p1∧¬p2)∨q(ii)⇔(Β¬p1∨q)∧(Β¬p2∨q)(iii)⇔(p1β†’q)∧(p2β†’q)(iv),
with justifications
  1. Rule 2 of our new Substitution Rules, where we substitute A=p1∨p2 into both sides of the construction of the conditional (Rule 10.a of Proposition 2.2.1);
  2. Rule 1 of our new Substitution Rules, using DeMorgan (Rule 9.a of Proposition 2.2.1) on the substatement Β¬(p1∨p2);
  3. distributivity (Rule 8.d of Proposition 2.2.1); and
  4. Rule 1 of our new Substitution Rules, using the construction of the conditional (Rule 10.a of Proposition 2.2.1) on each of the two β€œfactors” of the conjunction.
So our intuition about the logic of a disjunction in a conditional in this way was correct.